In this section, we’ll seek to answer the questions:
What is the Well-Ordering Principle?
What is mathematical induction, and how can we use it to prove statements about \(\N\text{?}\)
In this section we will assume the basic algebraic/arithmetic properties of the integers such as closure under addition, subtraction, and multiplication, most of which we will formalize via axioms in subsequent sections. Axiom 1.1.2 formalizes the familiar notion that nonempty subsets of the positive integers have a smallest element, which will be used repeatedly throughout the text. We then explore a closely related idea, mathematical induction, via an example and exercises.
Definition1.1.1.
The collection of natural numbers is denoted by \(\N\text{,}\) and is the set
By \(\N_0\) we mean the set \(\N\cup \set{0} = \set{0, 1, 2, 3, \ldots}\text{.}\)
In some sense, the fundamental properties of \(\N\) are (a) there is a smallest natural number, and (b) there is always a next natural numberIn fact, one can build a model of \(\N\) with set theory and the Peano axioms, which utilize the notion of a successor--the next natural number.). A consequence of the Peano postulates is the well-ordering principle, which we state as an axiom.
Axiom1.1.2.Well-Ordering Principle.
Every nonempty subset of \(\N_0\) contains a least (smallest) element under the usual ordering, \(\le\) 1
Our word choice is suggestive. In fact, other orderings do exist, and while the set of nonnegative real numbers \(\mathbb{R}\) does not satisfy the well-ordering principle under the usual ordering \(\le\text{,}\) the Well Ordering Axiom asserts that there exists a well ordering on any set, including \(\mathbb{R}\text{.}\) Accepting this axiom is equivalent to accepting the axiom of choice.
.
The Well-Ordering Principle is useful for producing smallest elements of nonempty subsets defined to have certain properties, as the following example demonstrates.
Exploration1.1.1.
In this exploration, we investigate polynomials with real coefficients, as well as their degrees. We will define these terms more formally in Definition 2.2.1, but for now you may use your intuition from previous courses in algebra.
Let \(S\) be the set of all polynomials \(f\) in the variable \(x\) with real coefficients such that \(f(2) = f(-2) = 0\) and \(f(0) = -4\text{.}\)
Give an example of an \(f\in S\) and \(g\notin S\text{.}\)
Let \(D = \setof{\deg f}{f\in S}\) be the set of possible degrees of polynomials in \(S\text{.}\) Show that \(D\ne \emptyset\) and \(D\subseteq \N_0\text{.}\)
Apply the Well-Ordering Principle to argue that \(D\) has a least element. To what does this correspond in \(S\text{?}\)
We will use this principle throughout the text, next in Theorem 1.2.5.
Definition1.1.4.
The set of integers consists of the positive and negative natural numbers, together with zero, and is denoted by \(\Z\text{:}\)
Let \(P(m)\) be a statement about the natural number \(m\) 3
Sample statements could include “\(m\) is really interesting” or “\(3m^2 + m + 2\) is even”.
. Let \(k_0\in \N\) be such that the statement \(P(k_0)\) is true (the base case), and suppose there is an \(n\ge k_0\) such that for all \(k\) satisfying \(k_0 \le k \le n\text{,}\)\(P(k)\) is true (the inductive hypothesis). Then \(P(n+1)\) is true, and thus \(P(m)\) is true for all \(m\ge k_0\) (the inductive step).
Mathematical induction is like climbing an infinite staircase. The base case tells us that we can take a first step on the staircase (\(k_0\)). In the inductive hypothesis, we assume we can take all the steps up to a certain height (\(n\)). In the inductive step, we prove that this allows us to take the \((n+1)\)st step.
Thus, if we can take step \(k_0\text{,}\) we can (by the inductive step) take step \(k_0 + 1\text{.}\) And since we can take step \(k_0 + 1\text{,}\) we can (again by the inductive step) take step \(k_0 + 2\text{.}\) And so on, forever (or, if the notion of actual infinity makes you uncomfortable, as far as we want to go).